Tuesday, March 17, 2015

Anti-Intellectualism in 21st-Century America

Rate: 2 Flag
When we consider that the United States was founded largely by intellectuals – Jefferson, Adams, Madison and others – it is ironic that we as a nation have rarely celebrated the value of intellect, except when it can be shown to produce financial gain.  This is amply documented in American historian Richard Hofstadter’s modern classic, Anti-intellectualism in American Life (1963), winner of the Pulitzer Prize for non-fiction in 1964.
Hofstadter defined anti-intellectualism broadly to refer to an attitude of “resentment and suspicion” toward the “critical, creative, and contemplative side of mind.”   He identified at least three distinct expressions of this attitude, which we may call anti-rationalism, anti-elitism, and unreflective instrumentalism .  Nearly thirty years after the book first appeared, I wrote an analytical essay examining its major themes and their continued relevance to American life (Rigney 1991).  
As we now approach the fiftieth anniversary of the book’s publication, it will be worth our while to revisit Hofstadter and to ask whether his diagnosis of our cultural condition is still pertinent today. This brief essay is based on, and offers some further reflections on, my previous article.

Anti-rationalism
                Hofstadter begins by analyzing anti-rationalism, which manifests itself as a suspicion and hostility toward the value of critical thought and reasoned discourse in general.  This form of anti-intellectualism, which tends to regard intellect as cold and passionless, has a long lineage in our history.  It is rooted particularly in the history of American Protestantism since the Great Awakening of the early 17th century. 
                    The Puritan ideal of the minister as an intellectual leader, Hofstadter writes, “was steadily weakened in the face of the evangelical ideal of the minister as a popular crusader and exhorter.”  This evangelical tradition lives on today in the emotional  appeal of charismatic and fundamentalist clergy, who commonly challenge the more secular culture of critical discourse, especially as it is practiced and propagated in modern universities. 
                   Conservative religious hostility toward modern science, and particularly toward the cosmology of the big bang, organic evolution and climate science, is rooted in this evangelical tradition.  The religious right directs hostility toward the humanities as well when they, like the sciences, seem to  relativize moral teachings, promote a secular worldview, and present a godless vision of the universe and our place in it.
                Underlying this religious anti-rationalism is the fear that critical discourse will challenge traditional sources of authority and thus undermine the foundations of absolute belief.  Hofstadter acknowledges that these fears are not entirely groundless.  Critical thinking really does threaten the unexamined  traditions of the past.  He writes that “left free, there is nothing it will not reconsider, analyze, throw into question.”  Authoritarian regimes, whether religious or secular, know this and suppress freedom of thought and speech accordingly.  In the domain of critical thinking, nothing is sacred – except perhaps  reasoned discourse itself.
                Today the culture of reasoned discourse appears to be at a low ebb in the United States.  Wars of words between traditional conservatives and more secular modernists fill the airwaves and the cables,  polarizing our national politics.  The messages propagated at the extremes – slogans, soundbites and simplistic talking points easily learned and repeated by uncritical thinkers – belie the increasing and frightening complexity of the realities they describe.  Such messages are fueled by what we might call complexiphobia in the public at large, the anxious yearning for simple answers in times that are anything but simple.

Anti-elitism
                A second kind of anti-intellectualism identified by Hofstadter, anti-elitism, manifests itself in the rise of populist political movements which express mistrust and resentment toward the educated elite and their presumed claims to superior knowledge and wisdom.  Public respect for the highly educated has waxed and waned through American history.         
                 Hofstadter notes that at the founding of the new republic, the leaders were the intellectuals.  Thomas Jefferson and his colleagues were drawn largely from a propertied and learned class, a class of gentlemen.  Soon after the founding, however,  this educated elite confronted opposition from a grass-roots populist upsurge represented most notably by Andrew Jackson, the rough and ready man of the people. 
                 Later, during the Progressive era, the nation gained a new respect for intellect, now represented by an emerging stratum of scholar-experts capable of helping  to manage the growing complexities of an industrial order.  The country elected Woodrow Wilson, former president of Princeton University, as its leader.
                In the twentieth century we have seen political expressions of anti-intellectualism on both the left and right.  On the left, Hostadter observes strains of anti-intellectualism in the blue-collar labor movement, expressing feelings of anger and resentment toward an educated elite drawn from the Ivy Leagues and other bastions of higher learning.  Blue-collar workers, whose educations were often earned in what Eugene Debs called the “hard school of human experience,” looked askance at booklearning.  The perception that the educated elite “thinks they’re better than we are” survives to this day in working-class populist culture.
                From the right, attacks on university faculties in the McCarthy era of the 1950’s, and later George Wallace’s tirade against what he called “pointy-headed intellectuals” in the 1960s, remind us that populism is not easily cast in simple left-right terms.  The contemporary Tea Party movement has effectively mobilized many of the same resentments that McCarthy and Wallace did, arousing hostility toward  “ liberal elitists” who “think they know what’s good for us.”
                Interestingly, conservative ideologists today frequently make a distinction between the cultural elite and the economic elite.  In this view, the former  includes most liberal media and politicians, Hollywood celebrities, and university professors, while the latter includes most corporate rich and super-rich.  Oddly, members of this financial elite largely escape populist wrath unless they are seen to have benefited outrageously from the recession that has left so many others without jobs or homes.  Populist anger toward liberal political elites in particular, whether deserved or not, appears to have played a significant role in the defeat of the Democratic Party in the recent mid-term Congressional elections, widely viewed as a rebuff of the policies of the Obama administration.
                Harvard historian James Kloppenberg, in his new book Reading Obama (2011: xv.; see also Cohen 2010), contends that Barak Obama is one of only a few intellectuals to have held the office of President in American history.  (Kloppenberg names Jefferson, Madison,  John and John Quincy Adams, and Lincoln as the others, with Wilson and the Roosevelts also honorably mentioned.) 
                  Perhaps indicative of our national tendency toward anti-intellectualism, the philosopher-president is a rare breed in our history.  No doubt many presidents have been intelligent, but few have been intellectual in Kloppenberg’s view.  The fact that Obama has muted his intellect in public when he talks to “the folks” in campaign appearances, displaying instead the common touch as he seeks to connect with his audiences at a personal level, suggests that populist anti-elitism is still alive and well in American politics.

Unreflective Instrumentalism
                Hofstadter identifies a third kind of anti-intellectualism, which I have elsewhere called unreflective instrumentalism, or the devaluation of forms of thought that do not promise relatively immediate payoffs.  In American culture, “payoffs” typically means money.  Instrumentalists want to know the cash value of an idea.  This attitude derives most directly, Hofstadter argues, from our predominant economic system, capitalism.  Instrumentalism is not inimical to reason per se, but only to reason which does not serve some “practical” end, such as making money. 
                But this attitude is usually held without much reflection.  It insists on practicality, but it never inquires very deeply into the meanings of the word “practical.”  Is a song or a painting practical?  Only if it makes  money.  Are pure mathematics and science practical?  Only if they result in the solution of “real world” problems – another phrase that is almost always invoked unreflectively.  Is philosophy a real-world activity?  One might argue, if arguments mattered to the anti-intellectual, that philosophy is in fact the most practical thing we possess – the basic operating system upon which all of our important decisions about reality are based.
                Hofstadter observes that how we value intellect is profoundly reflected in our views of education.  Some years ago the educator Alexander Astin (1987) conducted the first annual national survey of the attitudes of first-year college students.  Astin found that over several decades, undergraduates have trended steadily away from viewing the college years as a time to develop a meaningful philosophy of life.  Increasingly and overwhelmingly they, and probably their parents as well, now view higher education more instrumentally, as a means of pursuing material success. 
                  This attitude  is understandable enough in light of the hyperinflationary costs of higher education and the burden of debt that saddles most college students after graduation.  Moreover, the current job market for recent graduates is fiercely competitive, and the liberal arts are continually having to defend their value, as they should.  But to be a truly well-educated person is to be concerned, as the saying goes, not just with how to make a living, but with how to make a life.  Narrow vocationalism is a liability if it constricts the development of the whole person.  As I have written elsewhere (Rigney 1991:  447), neither bread nor philosophy is valuable as an end in itself,  but both are valuable for what they contribute to human well-being.  The perennial task of intellect is to reflect critically upon what ends, both material and ideal, are worth pursuing.
                We find unreflective tendencies in American culture not only in purely vocational conceptions of education, but also in the messages communicated via the mass media (both old and new) and popular entertainment, which are sometimes quite literally mindless.   We often hear  that we live in an “information age,” but this is also an age of misinformation and even disinformation.   If we are really living in the information age, then why are we so poorly informed?  Never before have the sources of our messages – cable news, Wikipedia and the web, Twitter, Facebook, i-things generally – been so diverse and needed such subtle and discerning intellectual skills to evaluate and interpret.   Never have we had such sophisticated communication technologies  as we have today. Yet have the quality of our messages, both incoming and outgoing, advanced with them?  What if we had the most advanced communication devices ever, but had little worth communicating through them?

             Anti-intellectualism, then , is no simple thing.  It takes multiple forms and derives from multiple sources in the dominant institutions of our culture.  Anti-rationalism has its roots largely in traditional religious institutions that seek to preserve elements of a simpler, pre-modern view of the world amid burgeoning complexity.  Anti-elitism finds its roots in populist political movements  that live on today in the resentments of the less advantaged.  Instrumentalism grows out of the material values and economic motivations of capitalism.  Each of these forms of anti-intellectualism has its own distinctive character and provenance; each poses its own distinctive threat toward educational policy and practice; and each persists and even thrives in contemporary American life.

REFERENCES:
Astin, Alexander. 1987.  “The American Freshman:  National Norms for Fall, 1986.” Los Angeles: Council on Education and UCLA.
Cohen, Patricia.  2010.  “In Writings of Obama, a Philosophy is Unearthed.”  New York Times, October     28: C1.
Hofstadter, Richard. 1963. Anti-intellectualism in American Life. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Kloppenberg, James T.  2011.  Reading Obama.  Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Rigney, Daniel.  1991, “Three Kinds of Anti-intellectualism.”  Sociological Inquiry 61 (4): 434-51.


Daniel Rigney is professor emeritus of sociology at St. Mary’s University in San Antonio and is  currently a Complimentary Visiting Scholar in the humanities at Rice University in Houston.  He can be contacted at drigney3@gmail.com.





No comments:

Post a Comment